Эротические рассказы

The Greatest Works of Immanuel Kant. Immanuel KantЧитать онлайн книгу.

The Greatest Works of Immanuel Kant - Immanuel Kant


Скачать книгу
on>

       Immanuel Kant

      The Greatest Works of Immanuel Kant

      Complete Critiques, Philosophical Works & Essays (Including Inaugural Dissertation & Biography)

       Published by

      

Books

      Advanced Digital Solutions & High-Quality eBook Formatting

       [email protected] 2017 OK Publishing ISBN 978-80-272-3236-9

      Table of Contents

       Introduction:

       IMMANUEL KANT by Robert Adamson

       KANT’S INAUGURAL DISSERTATION OF 1770

       The Three Critiques:

       THE CRITIQUE OF PURE REASON

       THE CRITIQUE OF PRACTICAL REASON

       THE CRITIQUE OF JUDGEMENT

       Critical Works:

       PROLEGOMENA TO ANY FUTURE METAPHYSICS

       FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS

       THE METAPHYSICS OF MORALS

       PHILOSOPHY OF LAW; OR, THE SCIENCE OF RIGHT

       THE METAPHYSICAL ELEMENTS OF ETHICS

       CRITICISM OF THE KANTIAN PHILOSOPHY by Arthur Schopenhauer

       Pre-Critical Works and Essays:

       DREAMS OF A SPIRIT-SEER

       IDEA OF A UNIVERSAL HISTORY ON A COSMOPOLITICAL PLAN

       Preface to THE METAPHYSICAL FOUNDATIONS OF NATURAL SCIENCE

       PERPETUAL PEACE: A Philosophical Essay

       OF THE INJUSTICE OF COUNTERFEITING BOOKS

      Introduction

       Table of Contents

      IMMANUEL KANT

       by Robert Adamson

       Table of Contents

      KANT, IMMANUEL (1724-1804), German philosopher, was born at Königsberg on the 22nd of April 1724. His grandfather was an emigrant from Scotland, and the name Cant is not uncommon in the north of Scotland, whence the family is said to have come. His father was a saddler in Königsberg, then a stronghold of Pietism, to the strong influence of which Kant was subjected in his early years. In his tenth year he was entered at the Collegium Fredericianum with the definite view of studying theology. His inclination at this time was towards classics, and he was recognized, with his school-fellow, David Ruhnken, as among the most promising classical scholars of the college. His taste for the greater Latin authors, particularly Lucretius, was never lost, and he acquired at school an unusual facility in Latin composition. With Greek authors he does not appear to have been equally familiar. During his university course, which began in 1740, Kant was principally attracted towards mathematics and physics. The lectures on classics do not seem to have satisfied him, and, though he attended courses on theology, and even preached on one or two occasions, he appears finally to have given up the intention of entering the Church. The last years of his university studies were much disturbed by poverty. His father died in 1746, and for nine years he was compelled to earn his own living as a private tutor. Although he disliked the life and was not specially qualified for it — as he used to say regarding the excellent precepts of his Pädagogik, he was never able to apply them — yet he added to his other accomplishments a grace and polish which he displayed ever afterwards to a degree somewhat unusual in a philosopher by profession.

      In 1755 Kant became tutor in the family of Count Kayserling. By the kindness of a friend named Richter, he was enabled to resume his university career, and in the autumn of that year he graduated as doctor and qualified as privatdocent. For fifteen years he continued to labour in this position, his fame as writer and lecturer steadily increasing. Though twice he failed to obtain a professorship at Königsberg, he steadily refused appointments elsewhere. The only academic preferment received by him during the lengthy probation was the post of under-librarian (1766). His lectures, at first mainly upon physics, gradually expanded until nearly all descriptions of philosophy were included under them.

      In 1770 he obtained the chair of logic and metaphysics at Konigsberg, and delivered as his inaugural address the dissertation De mundi sensibilis et intelligibilis forma et principiis. Eleven years later appeared the Kritik of Pure Reason, the work towards which he had been steadily advancing, and of which all his later writings are developments. In 1783 he published the Prolegomena, intended as an introduction to the Kritik, which had been found to stand in need of some explanatory comment. A second edition of the Kritik, with some modifications, appeared in 1787, after which it remained unaltered.

      In spite of its frequent obscurity, its novel terminology, and its declared opposition to prevailing systems, the Kantian philosophy made rapid progress in Germany. In the course of ten or twelve years from the publication of the Kritik of Pure Reason, it was expounded in all the leading universities, and it even penetrated into the schools of the Church of Rome. Such men as J. Schulz in Königsberg, J. G. Kiesewetter in Berlin, Jakob in Halle, Born and A. L. Heydenreich in Leipzig, K. L. Reinhold and E. Schmid in Jena, Buhle in Gottingen, Tennemann in Marburg, and Snell in Giessen, with many others, made it the basis of their philosophical teaching, while theologians like Tieftrunk, Stäudlin, and Ammon eagerly applied it to Christian doctrine and morality. Young men flocked to Königsberg as to a shrine of philosophy. The Prussian Government even undertook the expense of their support. Kant was hailed by some as a second Messiah. He was consulted as an oracle on all questions of casuistry — as, for example, on the lawfulness of inoculation for the small-pox. This universal


Скачать книгу
Яндекс.Метрика