Эротические рассказы

A Companion to Motion Pictures and Public Value. Группа авторовЧитать онлайн книгу.

A Companion to Motion Pictures and Public Value - Группа авторов


Скачать книгу
target="_blank" rel="nofollow" href="#ulink_e6b7f151-5408-5ee3-b0c4-4d9db6f2f3b5">13 Our thanks to Lucy Darwin, Xanthe Dobbie, Harrison Finch, Joerg Fingerhut, Timothy Hadwen, Jennifer A. McMahon, Richard Menary, and Robert Sinnerbrink for their lively engagement with this creative workshop. Quotations used herein are taken from transcripts of recordings made on October 18, 2018 at Macquarie University.

      Introduction

      Moral Value/Ethical Value

      Ted Nannicelli and Mette Hjort

      As Carl Plantinga insightfully notes in his chapter in this section, “When considering the public value of stories on screens, we are typically interested in the ethical implications of the experiences they offer” (p. 113, this volume). This fact is perhaps most apparent when audiences have strong negative reactions to the ethical perspective (or lack thereof) of a screen story—say, for example, in the case of A Serbian Film (2010), The House that Jack Built (2018), or 365 Days (2020). Such films are the most recent instances of motion pictures that spur debate about how the flawed ethical perspective of a motion picture might negatively influence the moral character of its viewers, potentially eroding our shared ethical principles or values. To get a sense of the long history of these kinds of concerns, one need only review the Motion Picture Production Code of 1930, which admonished, for example, that “crimes against the law” including theft, robbery, and murder “shall never be presented in such a way as to throw sympathy with the crime as against law and justice or to inspire others with a desire for imitation” (quoted in Doherty 1999, 361).

      As Ted Nannicelli notes in his chapter, the sort of approach to the ethics of motion pictures taken by Plantinga and Stadler, and much of the scholarship with which they engage, focuses on the fictional content of motion pictures and the ethics of attitude or perspective the film takes on that content and/or the ethics of the response it attempts to solicit from viewers. For example, Plantinga reviews an argument he has made previously, according to which 300 (2006) is an ethically flawed film insofar as it depicts the Persian characters as monstrous Others and “promotes fascist ideology” (p. 122, this volume; 2019b). While Plantinga is surely right that we are typically interested in these sorts of ethical implications, there are a number of other important dimensions of the ethical or moral value of motion pictures.

      Three of the chapters in this section—those by Sanders, Hjort, and Nannicelli—contribute to the development of an ethics of motion picture production. As Hjort and Nannicelli describe in their chapters, interest in the ethics of motion picture production has burgeoned in recent years. Hjort points out that “what is at stake here is how living beings—women, children, animals, and specific professional groups (actresses, stunt persons)—but also, for example, the natural environment are treated during the making of motion pictures” (p. 151, this volume). For this reason, the ethics of film production increasingly attracts the attention of a diverse group of scholars ranging from production studies (e.g., Martin 2012; Mayer 2014) to ecocriticism (e.g. Maxwell and Miller 2012; Vaughan 2019) to philosophy of art (e.g., Nannicelli 2014; Ponech 2014), and with a focus on all sorts of motion picture production from television charity drives (Ong 2016) to traditional, cinematic documentary (Hjort 2018) to interactive, web-based documentary (Sanders, this volume).

      Hjort persuasively argues that, in recent years, the #MeToo movement and the specter of an irreversible climate disaster have brought the topic of production ethics to the fore and, moreover, lent this research a particular urgency. Partly for this reason, ethical breaches or otherwise ethically dubious behavior, tends to be especially visible or, perhaps, what we first notice when exploring the ethics of motion picture production. However, it is important to recognize Hjort’s point that this research program’s “collective aims extend well beyond any mere documentation of unethical behaviour” (p. 151, this volume). On the contrary, other aims include, for example, “developing fairer practices” and “the introduction of regulatory changes” (p. 151, this volume).

      As a final prefatory remark, we should say something brief about how we and the authors in this section are using the terms “ethical” and “moral”. Roughly speaking, we are using these terms interchangeably to refer to matters relating to the rightness or wrongness of actions and the goodness or badness of dispositions or character traits. The sorts of questions at stake in this domain of inquiry include, for example: How should one act in a given situation? What is the right (or wrong) thing to do? By what principles should one live? And so forth. Some philosophers and theorists regard the moral as a subset of the ethical—more specifically, as a modern, Western conception of the ethical that emphasizes particular ethical concepts like obligation and duty (e.g., Williams [1985] 2011). We have no objections to this account or this usage. But there is another common usage of the term “moral”—as in “moral philosophy”—that is synonymous with “ethical,” and it is this usage that we follow here.

      References

      1 Asch, Timothy. 1992. “The Ethics of Ethnographic Film-Making.” In Film as Ethnography, edited by Peter Ian Crawford and David Turton, 196–204. Manchester: Manchester University Press.

      2 Doherty, Thomas. 1999. Pre-Code Hollywood: Sex, Immortality, and Insurrection in American Cinema, 1930–1934. New York: Columbia University Press.

      3 Gross, Larry, John Stuart Katz, and Jay Ruby, eds. 1988. Image Ethics: The Moral Rights of Subjects in Photographs, Film, and Television. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

      4 Hjort, Mette. 2018. “Guilt-Based Filmmaking: Moral Failures, Muddled Activism, and the ‘Dogumentary’ Get a Life.” Journal of Aesthetics & Culture 10 (2): 6–14.

      5 MacDougall, David. 1998. Transcultural Cinema. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

      6 Martin, Sylvia J. 2012. “Stunt Workers and Spectacle.” In Film and Risk, edited by Mette Hjort, 97–114. Detroit, MI: Wayne State University Press.

      7 Maxwell, Richard, and Toby Miller. 2012. Greening the Media. New York: Oxford University Press.

      8 Mayer,


Скачать книгу
Яндекс.Метрика