Fallible Authors. Alastair MinnisЧитать онлайн книгу.
a particularly acute way, given that the auctor was held to be not only a writer but also an “authority” in the sense of a person whose words were judged worthy of imitation and belief. An “immoral author” was therefore an oxymoron. Yet, in that period, many churchmen—and indeed many of their secular counterparts—displayed a disturbing number of shortcomings. Did such fallibilities devalue their authority, compromise their power, render their sacraments worthless, set their preaching at naught?
There was a name for the belief that the effectiveness of the sacraments depends on the moral character, the state of grace, of the minister: Donatism, after the controversial fourth-century bishop of Carthage, Donatus. The initiating cause seems to have been Bishop Felix of Aptunga’s collusion with the Emperor Diocletian’s persecution of Christians. This raised the question of whether the sacraments of one who had sinned so greatly against his fellows could possibly be valid, including his consecration of Donatus’s predecessor, Bishop Caecelian. Donatus won many adherents for the view that Caecelian’s consecration was invalid, and a schism developed in the church, the matter not being resolved until the Council of Carthage of 411, when Donatism was definitively hereticated. Approximately a thousand years later Chaucer’s contemporary John Wyclif fell into a version of that heresy—or, at least, was accused of having done so. (The nature and extent of Wyclif’s “Donatism” is a matter of some scholarly controversy, as my subsequent discussion will acknowledge.) His contemporary Geoffrey Chaucer created a character who declared that an immoral man can tell an effectively moral tale—a position that, inter alia, may be seen as a reflex of an orthodox reaction against Donatism. Or perhaps against that staple of Wycliffite thought, the conviction that power of any kind, whether spiritual or secular, depends on divine grace. Put simply, no pope, bishop, priest, or prince has true dominion (dominium) over his subjects while he lives in a state of mortal sin. It could be inferred that any spiritual authority which the Pardoner claims (whether rightly or wrongly, according to canon law) is devalued by his self-confessed viciousness. Herein lies the text’s major challenge.
Chaucer created another character, the Wife of Bath, who presents what was, by the standards of his day, an even greater challenge. A woman who displays in sensational form so many of the fallibilities then deemed endemic to her sex, dares to quote the Bible, bandy about authoritative documents just like a schoolman, enthusiastically defend female sexual desire, and tell a moral tale which suggests that true nobility comes from God alone and is unaffected by class or gender. And all this in an age in which Wycliffite nonconformity was developing the proposition that virtuous women had more right to preach than vicious men, and (in certain situations) could administer the sacraments—even that most controversial and contested sacrament of all, the Eucharist. Chaucer lived in interesting times.
This, inevitably, raises the issue of the poet’s attitude to Wycliffite thought. I certainly believe (I could not have written this book otherwise) that Chaucer was fascinated by ideas which, during his lifetime, became more and more dangerous to discuss, and which (in certain distinctive and extreme forms) were deemed heretical.5 But that, of course, does not make him a Wycliffite sympathizer, and the elusive figure who flits behind his works seems an unlikely victim of the repressive forces unleashed by Henry IV and Archbishop Arundel in their attempt to crush Lollardy.6 I fully support the claim of Alan J. Fletcher, who has done more than anyone else to theorize the question of Chaucer’s relationship with Wycliffism, that the poet “enlisted . . . ‘the culture of heresy’ in his writing.”7 But sometimes we disagree on the details of how this was done and the significance of that enlistment. My main general reservation concerns Fletcher’s adoption of the compound “radical/heretical discourse,” which, he explains, “attempts to contain the complex and shifting status of reformist ideology c. 1380–1420, a period during which many positions within that ideology, though originally orthodox, increasingly lost their orthodox respectability as they became characteristically colonized by the heretics.”8 That is well said, but we need not suppose that any apparently “radical” discourse inevitably became appropriated by heresy (and therefore, tout court, must be seen as heretical). The Lollards never gained a monopoly on (for example) criticism of deviant clergymen (especially with regard to preaching, pardons, and relics), unconventional deployment of auctoritees, outlandish treatment of marriage lore, or subversion of traditional gender-roles (not that Wyclif’s own theology gave any real encouragement to that, as I shall explain below). The fact that Chaucer was interested in such issues need not mean that he advocated them in some distinctively Lollard form, and the ways in which the poet chose to manipulate certain sensitive ideas is far removed from the uses to which they were put by Wyclif’s followers. (Besides, Chaucer merely glances at, or chooses to ignore, many of the matters that Lollards held most dear.)9 I would argue, furthermore, that the poet can be radical in ways which are either (broadly speaking) supportive of orthodoxy or according to its lights scandalous and maybe even subversive, without in any way entering the ideological empire of the heretics (whether their heartland or their colonized territories). The terms “radical” and “heretical,” as brought together in Alan Fletcher’s compound, are not inseparable companions.
Therefore I find highly appealing the model for reading dissent recently offered by Rita Copeland, which builds on Michel de Certeau’s recuperation of those materials (“resistances,” “survivals,” “delays,” etc.) that are held to be “irrelevant” to normative “understanding of the past,” or indeed threatening to the uniformity that such understanding imposes.10 Copeland emphasizes the possibility of “ideological difference and dissent within the ‘official’ domains of academic or clerical discourses as well as [emphasis mine] the more commonly recognized conflicts between the ‘official’ and the ‘heterodox.’” I too wish to resist the temptation to collapse the former into the latter, being eager to see restored “to the notion of dissent its dynamism and elasticity as a gesture of difference.”11 Many such gestures were never named as heterodoxy, sedition, or heresy. While “the ‘habit’ of dissent” certainly “found expression through the vehicle of popular heresies,”12 this was far from being its only (or necessarily its most culturally significant) vehicle. Dissent, difference, radicalism—call it what you will— existed far beyond the boundaries of juridical denunciation, whether religious or secular. It frequently resisted colonization by “heretics”—or “heretics” did not deem it worthy of their colonization. The radicalism of Chaucer’s Pardoner’s Prologue and Tale and Wife of Bath’s Prologue and Tale is, I believe, of that order: not a determinate of Lollard heresy but rather an array of gestures of difference which is uniquely Chaucer’s own.
I dedicate Fallible Authors to my daughters: to Sarah and Katherine, with love from your fallible father.
INTRODUCTION
Authority and Fallibility in Medieval Textual Culture
“We elected a president, not a pope,” Barbra Streisand is reported to have said of Bill Clinton, when the allegations about his sexual escapades were flying thick and fast.1 Betty Friedan agreed: “It is of no consequence to me what Clinton does in his private life. . . . All that is important is his public policies.”2 Other voices condemned him for falling beneath “the standard of behavior we expect from Presidents,”3 for having brought the high office of the President of the United States into disrepute. “Though elected by people and filled by men,” this “office has a sacred quality,” wrote Hugo Young.4 “The most powerful democracy in the world invests its leader with a special eminence as head of state as well as head of government.” And yet— though Clinton “set a bad example” and “certainly [is] not a man of character,” his “lies weren’t about public business.” Young continues: “He wasn’t caught knowing from the start that the Sudan factory he bombed had nothing to do with lethal weaponry. In a quotidian matter, he lied.” Moving from 1998 to 2005, and to another president, the situation seems to have been reversed. A major cause of then-current anxiety was whether George W. Bush, marketed to the American people as a “man of character” (with the probity of his personal life apparently unassailable), knew from the start that Saddam Hussein had little if anything to do with the perpetrators of the