Эротические рассказы

Plato: The Complete Works (31 Books). Plato Читать онлайн книгу.

Plato: The Complete Works (31 Books) - Plato


Скачать книгу
this way: a friend is the friend of some one; is he not?

      Certainly he is.

      And has he a motive and object in being a friend, or has he no motive and object?

      He has a motive and object.

      And is the object which makes him a friend, dear to him, or neither dear nor hateful to him?

      I do not quite follow you, he said.

      I do not wonder at that, I said. But perhaps, if I put the matter in another way, you will be able to follow me, and my own meaning will be clearer to myself. The sick man, as I was just now saying, is the friend of the physician—is he not?

      Yes.

      And he is the friend of the physician because of disease, and for the sake of health?

      Yes.

      And disease is an evil?

      Certainly.

      And what of health? I said. Is that good or evil, or neither?

      Good, he replied.

      And we were saying, I believe, that the body being neither good nor evil, because of disease, that is to say because of evil, is the friend of medicine, and medicine is a good: and medicine has entered into this friendship for the sake of health, and health is a good.

      True.

      And is health a friend, or not a friend?

      A friend.

      And disease is an enemy?

      Yes.

      Then that which is neither good nor evil is the friend of the good because of the evil and hateful, and for the sake of the good and the friend?

      Clearly.

      Then the friend is a friend for the sake of the friend, and because of the enemy?

      That is to be inferred.

      Then at this point, my boys, let us take heed, and be on our guard against deceptions. I will not again repeat that the friend is the friend of the friend, and the like of the like, which has been declared by us to be an impossibility; but, in order that this new statement may not delude us, let us attentively examine another point, which I will proceed to explain: Medicine, as we were saying, is a friend, or dear to us for the sake of health?

      Yes.

      And health is also dear?

      Certainly.

      And if dear, then dear for the sake of something?

      Yes.

      And surely this object must also be dear, as is implied in our previous admissions?

      Yes.

      And that something dear involves something else dear?

      Yes.

      But then, proceeding in this way, shall we not arrive at some first principle of friendship or dearness which is not capable of being referred to any other, for the sake of which, as we maintain, all other things are dear, and, having there arrived, we shall stop?

      True.

      My fear is that all those other things, which, as we say, are dear for the sake of another, are illusions and deceptions only, but where that first principle is, there is the true ideal of friendship. Let me put the matter thus: Suppose the case of a great treasure (this may be a son, who is more precious to his father than all his other treasures); would not the father, who values his son above all things, value other things also for the sake of his son? I mean, for instance, if he knew that his son had drunk hemlock, and the father thought that wine would save him, he would value the wine?

      He would.

      And also the vessel which contains the wine?

      Certainly.

      But does he therefore value the three measures of wine, or the earthen vessel which contains them, equally with his son? Is not this rather the true state of the case? All his anxiety has regard not to the means which are provided for the sake of an object, but to the object for the sake of which they are provided. And although we may often say that gold and silver are highly valued by us, that is not the truth; for there is a further object, whatever it may be, which we value most of all, and for the sake of which gold and all our other possessions are acquired by us. Am I not right?

      Yes, certainly.

      And may not the same be said of the friend? That which is only dear to us for the sake of something else is improperly said to be dear, but the truly dear is that in which all these so-called dear friendships terminate.

      That, he said, appears to be true.

      And the truly dear or ultimate principle of friendship is not for the sake of any other or further dear.

      True.

      Then we have done with the notion that friendship has any further object. May we then infer that the good is the friend?

      I think so.

      And the good is loved for the sake of the evil? Let me put the case in this way: Suppose that of the three principles, good, evil, and that which is neither good nor evil, there remained only the good and the neutral, and that evil went far away, and in no way affected soul or body, nor ever at all that class of things which, as we say, are neither good nor evil in themselves;—would the good be of any use, or other than useless to us? For if there were nothing to hurt us any longer, we should have no need of anything that would do us good. Then would be clearly seen that we did but love and desire the good because of the evil, and as the remedy of the evil, which was the disease; but if there had been no disease, there would have been no need of a remedy. Is not this the nature of the good—to be loved by us who are placed between the two, because of the evil? but there is no use in the good for its own sake.

      I suppose not.

      Then the final principle of friendship, in which all other friendships terminated, those, I mean, which are relatively dear and for the sake of something else, is of another and a different nature from them. For they are called dear because of another dear or friend. But with the true friend or dear, the case is quite the reverse; for that is proved to be dear because of the hated, and if the hated were away it would be no longer dear.

      Very true, he replied: at any rate not if our present view holds good.

      But, oh! will you tell me, I said, whether if evil were to perish, we should hunger any more, or thirst any more, or have any similar desire? Or may we suppose that hunger will remain while men and animals remain, but not so as to be hurtful? And the same of thirst and the other desires,— that they will remain, but will not be evil because evil has perished? Or rather shall I say, that to ask what either will be then or will not be is ridiculous, for who knows? This we do know, that in our present condition hunger may injure us, and may also benefit us:—Is not that true?

      Yes.

      And in like manner thirst or any similar desire may sometimes be a good and sometimes an evil to us, and sometimes neither one nor the other?

      To be sure.

      But is there any reason why, because evil perishes, that which is not evil should perish with it?

      None.

      Then, even if evil perishes, the desires which are neither good nor evil will remain?

      Clearly they will.

      And must not a man love that which he desires and affects?

      He must.

      Then, even if evil perishes, there may still remain some elements of love or friendship?

      Yes.

      But not if evil is the cause of friendship: for in that case nothing will be the friend of any other thing after the destruction of evil; for the effect cannot remain when the cause is destroyed.

      True.

      And


Скачать книгу
Яндекс.Метрика