Freedom of the Border. Paul SchefferЧитать онлайн книгу.
the new world disorder and discuss various ideas about the future of the European Union (Part III).
It is a triptych concerned first with the significance of attachment to place in a time of globalization, then with the crossing of borders, which creates new fault lines in society, and lastly with possible ways of reconciling freedom and security in Europe. It explores the questions lurking behind the reality of the euro crisis, the refugee crisis and populism. Can the gap be closed between citizens who are looking for protection and citizens who embrace openness?
Notes
1 1 Paul Scheffer, ‘De doos van Pandora’, De Haagse Post, 31 March 1990, pp. 34–9.
2 2 Paul Scheffer, Alles doet mee aan de werkelijkheid: Herman Wolf 1893–1942, Amsterdam, De Bezige Bij, 2013.
3 3 Martin Walser, Deutsche Sorgen, Frankfurt am Main, Suhrkamp, 1997.
4 4 Günter Grass, Deutscher Lastenausgleich, Munich, dtv, 1993.
5 5 Martin Walser, Erfahrungen beim Verfassen einer Sonntagsrede, Frankfurt am Main, Suhrkamp, 1998.
6 6 Arnulf Baring, Unser neuer Größenwahn, Stuttgart, Deutsche Verlagsanstalt, 1989.
7 7 Ryszard Kapuściński, Lapidarium, transl. Martin Pollack, Frankfurt am Main, Fischer, 1996 (originally published in five volumes as Lapidarium, Warsaw, 1990, 1995, 1997, 2000, 2002). English by the translator.
8 8 J. A. van Hamel, Nederland tusschen de mogendheden, Amsterdam, Van Holkema & Warendorf, 1918, p. 387.
9 9 Harry Mulisch, Bij gelegenheid, Amsterdam, De Bezige Bij, 1995, p. 34.
10 10 See Paul Scheffer, ‘De ontvoering van Europa’, NRC Handelsblad, 18 October 1993.
11 11 Geert van Istendael, Le labyrinth belge, transl. Vincent Marnix and Monique Nagielkopf, Bordeaux, Le Castor Astral, 2004, p. 271.
12 12 C. P. Cavafy, Collected Poems, transl. Edmund Keeley and Philip Sherrard, Princeton, NJ, Princeton University Press, 1975, p. 18.
13 13 Peter Sloterdijk, in ‘Wachten op de barbaren’ (VPRO television), 31 March 1996.
14 14 G. W. F. Hegel, Die Wissenschaft der Logik, Frankfurt am Main, Suhrkamp, 1970, p. 197.
15 15 Paulo Giordano, How Contagion Works: Science, Awareness and Community in Times of Global Crises, transl. Alex Valente, London, Weidenfeld & Nicolson, 2020, p. 24.
16 16 See for example Mark Schaevers, ‘Het multiculturele debat: Paul Scheffer en Arnon Grunberg kruisen de degens’, Humo, 9 February 2018.
17 17 Zygmunt Bauman, Community: Seeking Safety in an Insecure World, Cambridge, Polity, 2001, p. 19.
Discovery of the world citizen
In The Complaint of Peace, Erasmus remarks that the most trifling matters are used to sow division.
Thus, for instance, an Englishman, say they, is the natural enemy of a Frenchman, because he is a Frenchman. A man born on this side the river Tweed must hate a Scotchman, because he is a Scotchman. A German naturally disagrees with a Frank; a Spaniard with both. … A name is nothing; but there are many circumstances, very important realities, which ought to endear and unite men of different nations. As an Englishman, you bear ill-will to a Frenchman. Why not rather, as a man to a man, do you not bear him good will?1
Here we see a cosmopolitanism that wishes to embrace humanity and regards national, religious or ethnic differences as of lesser importance. It is cosmopolitanism as a form of pacifism, a principled appeal for the bridging of differences in order to create lasting peace. This tradition in European thought is both important and controversial, and we will discuss it here mainly in the light of work by philosophers Desiderius Erasmus and Immanuel Kant.
By starting with a brief history of ideas, I aim to make clear how long it took to develop an ideal of equality that attempted to reach beyond borders. It turns out to be far from natural to prioritize humanity as a whole. In fact the French, Germans and Spaniards – to say nothing of the Scots – attach great significance to their own unique character. This detour through philosophy is crucial partly because it demonstrates the degree to which thinkers like Erasmus and Kant, for all their cosmopolitan principles, were trapped in preconceived ideas with a religious or nationalist tenor.
Anyone contemplating what the cosmopolitanism and pacifism of Erasmus and Kant have to say to today’s Europe will encounter a number of difficulties. How can we bridge so many centuries? What can their thinking mean for us? Erasmus and Kant were products of their time, but they were also far ahead of it. Perhaps that contradiction can help us; perhaps the limitations of their thinking can broaden our view.
The starting point for any consideration of citizenship lies in antiquity. Philosophers including Plato and Aristotle conceived of the polis as a limited circle of citizens. Far from everyone who lived in the city could claim citizenship; slaves, women and resident foreigners did not qualify. Citizenship was also clearly delineated to exclude the ‘barbarians’ on the outside. So the ideal of equality formulated in Athens cannot be regarded as a direct forerunner of modern ideas about the equality of all human beings.2
A fundamental belief in world citizenship arises only with later forms of classical philosophy, especially with the stoics of the third century BCE. In the words of the originator of Stoicism, Zeno, we ‘should not live divided by cities, towns and divers countries, separated by distinct laws, rights and customs’. Rather we must live such that we look upon all people as ‘our fellow citizens, and of the same country’.3 In the work of Seneca, Marcus Aurelius and others, this stance is developed further.
Among the stoics, cosmopolitanism is an ethical theory based on the notion that people are bound together by shared rationality.4 Reason resides above all in the capacity to reach moral judgements. It unites people irrespective of where they were born. In theory all citizens are part of a moral community that can have no borders. World citizenship of this kind is compatible with citizenship of a specific city or state.
Cosmopolitanism is interpreted in this way by thinkers including Marcus Aurelius. In his Meditations he writes,
If our intellectual part is common, the reason also, in respect of which we are rational beings, is common: if this is so, common also is the reason which commands us what to do, and what not to do; if this is so, there is a common law also; if this is so, we are fellow-citizens; if this is so, we are members of some political community; if this is so, the world is in a manner a state. For of what other common political community will anyone say that the whole human race are members?5
According to the stoics, human relationships consist of concentric circles, from the closest, like the family, to the most universal. To this view of the world belongs the capacity to look from the perspective of others, no matter how strange or even hostile those others may be. Marcus Aurelius believes the mutual dependency and connectedness of human beings invites empathy. ‘Just as it is with the members in those bodies which are united in one, so it is with rational beings which exist separate, for they have been constituted for one co-operation.’6
Our loyalty must be to humanity as a whole before anything else. The accident of birth has no moral significance. Whatever their origins, all human beings have an equal right to be respected. To quote Marcus Aurelius again, ‘For it makes no difference whether a man lives there or here, if he lives everywhere in the world as in a state.’7 A long time passed before this idea met with a broadly sympathetic response in Europe.
After the end of classical antiquity, the Renaissance was the next important period for cosmopolitanism as an ideal. Particularly significant in this regard is the work of the humanist Desiderius Erasmus.